Philosophy Books » Philosophy of Mind

The best books on Consciousness

recommended by Susan Blackmore

Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction by Susan Blackmore

Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction
by Susan Blackmore

Read

The ‘hard problem’ of consciousness – of how the physical matter of the brain produces the psychological phenomenon of consciousness – has dogged psychologists and neuroscientists for decades. But what if we've been posing the question incorrectly all this time? The psychologist Susan Blackmore discusses five key texts that tackle this quicksilver concept.

Interview by Nigel Warburton

Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction by Susan Blackmore

Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction
by Susan Blackmore

Read

You had an out-of-body experience and that had some influence on your interest in consciousness. Let’s begin by discussing that experience.

It’s the whole story of my life, really. I’ve talked about it such a lot. It was a dramatic two-and-a-half-hour out-of-body experience that I had as a student­­, possibly provoked by a mixture of sleep deprivation and cannabis. Looking back, it’s hard to know what caused it. But it was so vivid and so completely and utterly realistic that everything I saw seemed to be more real than real. I felt more myself and more alive than I’d ever felt before. And, of course, I couldn’t explain it. This happened in 1970, which was my first year as a student of psychology in Oxford. I jumped to all sorts of wild conclusions about the paranormal, probably because the experience seemed so real. I became convinced of telepathy and clairvoyance, precognition and psychokinesis, life after death and souls and spirits and everything. So, I decided I would devote my life to proving all this stuff to the closed-minded scientists out there. That’s why I became a parapsychologist. I did my PhD on telepathy and clairvoyance. I trained as a witch and I got a crystal ball and read the Tarot cards and the I Ching. All of that. But my experimental results got me nowhere. I never found any convincing evidence of paranormal phenomena at all.

Back in the 1970s and early 1980s, there was no way I could understand how an out-of-body experience could be a natural phenomenon. I tried my absolute best and I wrote my first book on the subject called Beyond the Body which came out in 1982. I really tried there with what little psychology we had then – we had no neuroscience to speak of – to try to understand how it could be a natural phenomenon. The book is still read and still considered to be a sceptical classic, but it was very unsatisfactory. By then, I had more or less despaired of finding any paranormal phenomenon. I went on doing parapsychology for some time after that but eventually gave up because it was hopeless. This, to answer your question, is what led to me to think: well, I can’t see any evidence for astral bodies and souls and spirits that actually leave the body and go anywhere, and I can’t find any evidence of paranormal phenomena of any kind, so, what on earth was going on when I had that experience? I realised then that the whole excursion into the paranormal was a red herring and wasn’t helping me understand the experience at all. I began to realise, gradually, that the questions went much deeper than being just about out-of-body experiences. We’re coming on now to the early 1990s when it was finally becoming possible to mention the word ‘consciousness’ in respectable academic circles without being told to shut up.

Was it the influence of behaviourism that made psychologists reluctant to discuss consciousness?

Yes, indeed. When I was an undergraduate in psychology and physiology, from 1970 to 1973, there was no way that you could talk about consciousness to your lecturers. But that was beginning to break down for a variety of reasons. Research on imagery, for example, was a help. And the discoveries of internal things going on in the mind which challenged behaviourism and so on. But then in 1991, Dan Dennett’s book Consciousness Explained came out. And in 1994, the first Tucson conference on consciousness was started in Arizona, and it began to be possible to talk about consciousness. Meanwhile, I took over the socio-ecology course of a biologist friend of mine, John Crook at Bristol University, because he wanted to give up lecturing in order to devote himself to his Zen practice and run more retreats. His course had bits of consciousness in it, and I turned it into a consciousness course. And from then on, I started avidly reading everything on consciousness that I could get hold of.

Can we go back to your experience? When you felt that you were outside of your body, did you actually see your body lying down?

It was late one night and some of us in the student Psychical Research Society had been messing about with an Ouija board. This means you’re holding your arm out for hours on a glass that’s moving around. So, you get to feel a bit disconnected from your arm, and your body image goes a bit wonky. I was very sleep deprived – having such a good time staying up late, whilst getting up for 9am lectures as well. And I’d smoked a little bit of cannabis. I was sitting listening to the music on the floor with my two friends when I started going down a tunnel. It was when my friend Kevin asked me: ‘where are you, Sue?’ that I had to sort of think – yes, where am I? I couldn’t tell him I was in a tunnel. Everything was blurry and I was drifting. Then everything went clear as though I was on the ceiling looking down and I could see him, my other friend and myself sitting there on the floor. It absolutely seemed realistic. Later on, after I’d travelled for an hour and then came back, everything looked weird. My body was brown and didn’t have a head anymore. It had a jagged neck and was hollow.

Get the weekly Five Books newsletter

It became weirder and weirder as it went on. It’s more like an impression. If you’d been able to take a picture of what I saw, I don’t think it would have been realistic. But, to me, it appeared the most vivid and most realistic thing you could imagine. Everything was absolutely bright and sparkly and clear. And from up there I could see the three of us. I could see a silver cord coming from the body down there going into my tummy in my other body up there. Then I went off travelling. And all the time, Kevin was asking me questions which I’m sure is the reason why the experience lasted so long. In these situations people usually get scared and consequently most out-of-body experiences, OBEs, last only a few seconds or a few minutes. Some experts can have long ones but most ordinary spontaneous ones are very short. But I think Kevin asking me questions like ‘what’s going on there?’, and ‘can you fly?’, and ‘have you got wings?’ kept me from being scared, and so I just kept on going.

I should add that the experience ended with a mystical experience of oneness. I had tried to get back into my body for a second time but became too small, so I tried to grow to the right size and instead I just got bigger and bigger, expanding and expanding until I became everything. At that time I knew nothing about mystical experiences, but like so many mystics have said, I felt I was not separate from anything else, there was no distinct ‘me’ and ‘it.’ It was a classic experience of non-duality. This final part of the experience was probably what drove me into trying to understand consciousness, because it provoked that question: who am I? If I can become one with everything, then who am I really? I remember having to tell myself to go back inside my body and look out through the eyes. It was as if I had to re-enact the illusion of self. I was re-enacting or revivifying what I take for granted normally: that I am somehow a conscious being inside my body, looking out.

Can you now give an adequate explanation of what happened?

Adequate, yes, but complete, no. We do understand the tunnel. It’s a common experience in altered states of consciousness and is induced by random activity in the visual system, especially in primary visual cortex due to the way the cells there are organised. That’s been known for a long time, but the mystery of the OBE itself is only now being solved. Indeed OBEs are at last being investigated by serious psychologists and neuroscientists – something I never thought likely to happen!

A critical discovery was made by a Swiss neurosurgeon, Olaf Blanke, when he was stimulating an epileptic woman’s brain with subdural electrodes, trying to find the epileptic focus. To his, and her, surprise, he found that when he stimulated a spot at the right temporoparietal junction with very low intensity stimulation, this produced bodily distortions – a sense of floating, drifting, getting longer or shorter, thinner or fatter. Then when he applied a stronger stimulus, it produced full blown out-of-body experiences. He could even control the experiences. From then on, the new research started, confirming the importance of this part of the brain. What makes this so significant, and really throws out all those old theories of astral projection and departing souls, is the role of this brain area in constructing the sense of self. This is where the brain maintains our ‘body schema’, the constantly updated model of our whole body with its changing position and actions. Without this we could not act or move at all. This is then connected with other brain areas to our memories, sense of agency, decision making and so on. So now things begin to make sense. If this area is disrupted the body schema goes haywire and we are no longer ‘in’ our own body.

“Out-of-body experiences are at last being investigated by serious psychologists and neuroscientists”

I find it rather satisfyingly wonderful to understand that that’s what’s going on and we don’t need to suppose that anything actually leaves the body at all.  It also fits with the old astral projection literature where you find that people like Oliver Fox and Sylvan Muldoon, these famous astral projectors,  also reported bodily distortions and a sense of stretching and pulling and floating before their ‘projections’ took place. They didn’t have the science to understand it, so they invented the seven bodies of man and the different planes and the different spirits that inhabit the different planes, and so on. I can see why they did it. But it’s all tosh. It’s just not true. Some people find this sad and disappointing. To me, thinking of my own experiences and my continuing explorations of states of consciousness, it’s thrilling.

Let’s get to the five books. You’ve chosen some excellent ones. The first is Consciousness Explained (1991) by Daniel Dennett. It’s a bold title because if there’s one thing about consciousness it’s that people are struggling to understand what it is. The title suggests he’s just going to tell you that this is what the answer is.

Yes, he is going to tell you what the answer is to a point. But he’s not going to say ‘this is what consciousness is.’ He says ‘this is what you thought consciousness was, and you were wrong.’ The main point he’s making throughout is that you have to give up your intuitions. He uses wonderful examples that I love to make his points. I should say, though, that some readers don’t love them. If anyone is reading this and they try that book and hate it, then give up. It seems that people go in two directions: they either love the way he writes, or they hate it. I love it, with all his mad examples and neologisms. He’s dismantling a whole lot of illusions and saying that when you dismantle them the ‘hard problem’ has disappeared. We still can’t solve all the mysteries about it; there’s still a lot more to understand; but the problem is not what you thought it was. At least, that’s my interpretation of what he meant by Consciousness Explained.

The ‘hard problem’ is how the physical stuff of the brain and the body could give rise to the phenomena of consciousness, the feeling that we are experiencing the world and monitoring it in certain sorts of ways.

And you’ve tied yourself into a problem there, as did David Chalmers who invented the term ‘hard problem’, by saying ‘giving rise.’ As soon as you say ‘you’ve got this matter’ and ‘you’ve got this stuff called consciousness’, and you’ve got consciousness arising from it, then you’ve committed yourself to a kind of dualism. It may not be substance dualism or ontological dualism, but it’s some kind of dualism that you’ve committed yourself to because you’ve still got two things – matter and consciousness.

Many people – myself and Dan Dennett included – would say that this is an ill-posed problem. We can’t actually pose the problem better yet, though we can ask better questions. Where I really agree with Dan Dennett is that this is the job that we need to do first. We need to expose all the illusions and delusions that we have about our own minds before we can even begin to know what the right questions are to ask about experience. What we’re talking about is this: this subjective experience…We’re doing this interview by Skype, and it’s your experience of staring at me on a computer screen, and my experience of staring at you on a screen. That’s what we’re trying to account for.

Dennett is not saying that that experience doesn’t exist. He’s saying it’s not what you thought it was. He begins the book with him sitting in a rocking chair and experiencing the light on the leaves and so on. That’s what he’s talking about. People accuse him of explaining consciousness away, but he’s actually talking about immediate experience and trying to understand it. He’s saying here are all the illusions, let’s get them out of the way first.

What kind of illusions does Dennett want to cure us of?

The main one is the non-existence of what he labels the ‘Cartesian theatre.’ I think his book is an extended riff on rejecting this illusion. The point he makes is this: nearly everyone rejects Cartesian dualism because, for obvious reasons, it doesn’t work. But when they do so, they fail to throw out the idea of the audience who sits in the brain watching a screen, as it were, in the theatre. He calls this the ‘Cartesian theatre’ because it’s a sort of vestige of Cartesian dualistic thinking that remains even if you’ve thrown out the ontological dualism itself. I think he’s right about that. He calls people who think this way ‘Cartesian materialists.’

I write ‘CM’ in every book I’m reading again and again when people say things like ‘and then this entered consciousness’ or ‘this perception became conscious’ or ‘this became part of the contents of consciousness.’ All these are dead giveaways that you are still thinking in terms something like this: there are some processes going on in the brain that are conscious, and there are some that are not consciousness. Therefore, what we have to do is understand the difference between the conscious processes and the unconsciousness processes. That is where the whole hunt for the ‘neural correlates of consciousness’ comes from. But if you take Dennett’s ideas seriously, as I do, then all this is complete nonsense.

“We’re so deluded about what consciousness is that we need to throw out this distinction and start again”

In fact, where he ends up – and I end up somewhere similar – is saying that we’re so deluded about what consciousness is that we need to throw out this distinction and start again. In fact, I would argue, consciousness is an attribution we make. We attribute consciousness to certain perceptions that we have and certain actions that we do – usually after the fact or while we’re doing it – and therefore we believe in a continuous stream of consciousness, and we believe in a continuous self, and all of these things which aren’t true. This is how we become deluded. We imagine this stream of consciousness on the screen and we imagine ourselves having those experiences.

In reality, there are just brain processes going on. He develops his multiple drafts theory out of this to say that there are lots and lots of versions of any perceptions going through the brain. The critical point is that it’s not that some are really conscious, and the rest unconscious. That is only an attribution that we put on a perception if we get enough access to it, can speak about it, can act upon it and so on. That’s why he calls it ‘fame in the brain.’ When something spreads enough in the brain, then it can cause you to press a button or talk to someone and say ‘I’m conscious of looking at you now.’ There is nothing more to consciousness than that. That’s what he meant by ‘consciousness explained.’ That book came out in 1991 and has been widely read yet, 26 years on, I would say the majority of researchers in consciousness studies are still what he would call Cartesian materialists.

You’ve chosen William James’s The Principles of Psychology (1890) as your second book. He gives such a rich account of the phenomena of consciousness. I remember the “buzzing, blooming confusion.”

He does, although he doesn’t mention the word ‘consciousness’ that much. He did coin the term ‘stream of consciousness’, though he talks much more about the ‘stream of thought.’

The whole book is two volumes – 1,400 pages – and the chapter on consciousness of self is over one hundred pages, and is absolutely amazingly wonderful. My first degree was heavily behaviourist with rats running in mazes and that kind of thing. Cognitive psychology was just beginning towards the end of my degree, and so I went into that and lots of information processing stuff. It was only ages later when I got interested in consciousness that I read my copy of James’s book. I must tell you that my copy is a first edition, previously owned by the British prime minister Arthur Balfour and has his annotations in pencil all over it. I bought it for £12.50 at the Society for Psychical Research in 1981. Out of all the books I own, this is my absolute treasure.

“Out of all the books I own, this is my absolute treasure”

When I finally came to read it, I read the entire thing from cover to cover, which took me a while. It is marvellous – fantastic. His thinking is so subtle. What I love about James is when we knows something for sure – some experiment or something – then he will tell you so; but when he doesn’t, he goes into these wonderful explorations never really coming to a conclusion. I find his thoughts on the self very hard to understand, but I love the idea that he says there are ‘thoughts’ and then there are big ‘Thoughts’ which is me and my being: the self who has these thoughts. The ‘Thought’ owns this thought, as it were, like a herdsman would have a herd of cows. But then your attention shifts and the first herdsman disappears. Soon another Thought arrives and takes over the same herd of cows, wrongly assuming it’s the same herdsman – the same ‘me’ – as before. We simply don’t notice these shifts and so the illusion of being a continuous self is made.

He’s trying to draw out how the continuous self could be an illusion. And he’s struggling with this and giving these analogies, trying to understand it. I love that he doesn’t come down with a settled theory. He compares the automaton theory with the soul theory and while he does come down on one side in the end, he does it very cautiously and I just think it’s a wonderful show of someone brilliant putting what facts he can in, but then using them to struggle with the difficulty of the nature of mind, self, and consciousness. And sometimes when I’m smoking my evening joint and thinking about the nature of the universe, I think of him and Descartes and other wonderful thinkers who have struggled, and I think to myself ‘yes, it is this difficult. Keep going!’

Like Dennett, William James is also a superb writer. From the reader’s perspective, it’s a great joy to read passages even if you don’t agree with what he’s saying. All the books you’ve chosen for this interview contain really good writing.

I’m a very slow reader and so I can’t struggle with bad writing. I find it really hard to read fiction. I get so bored so quickly. There’s got to be something meaty and interesting and aggravating that will make me keep reading, because I find it such an arduous thing to do. With something like William James’s 1,400 pages, they kept me going! He lures you on from one thought to another and helps you to follow these complex ideas. It’s great.

Would you really recommend this to a modern reader who wants to find out about consciousness?

I would tell them to have a look at it and particularly that chapter on consciousness of the self. What I would do with that book now, confronted with it, is read the beginning and end of each chapter – he does summarise quite well and you will get the gist of it and get a feel for the period and what he knew.

He does the most wonderful thing at the beginning of the book. In a sort of foreword, he starts out by telling you what psychology assumes and you can tell from the way he writes that he’s not entirely happy about this but he’s got to start somewhere. He writes:

Psychology, the science of finite individual minds, assumes as its data (1) thoughts and feelings, and (2) a physical world in time and space with which they coexist and which (3) they know.

He’s putting down there the whole dualist problem right at the beginning. He’s saying that psychology just assumes this duality between (a) thoughts and feelings and (b) the physical world. He puts these things so clearly and that makes me want to read more. So, I think I would say to a modern reader, read his two-page introduction and read the beginning and end of bits. It’s absolutely full of gems. But in the modern world, who is going to read 1,400 pages? Indeed, he says that in the little foreword. He says:

The work has grown to a length which no one can regret more than the writer himself. The man must indeed be sanguine who, in this crowded age, can hope to have many readers for fourteen hundred continuous pages from his pen.

If only he were here now. I’d love to show him the modern world and how busy we are…

Your third book is The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind (1976) by Julian Jaynes. This is the book that very influentially discusses the idea of separate roles for the two hemispheres of the brain, isn’t it?

Yes. The book is famous for reasons that are not why I’ve chosen it. Jaynes’s argument is something like this: we all have different parts of our brains and we all sort of hear voices going on in our heads. But we, in the modern world, attribute those voices to things going on in our heads. When we hear our thoughts almost spoken to ourselves, we accept that those are our thoughts. Jaynes is an expert in ancient literature and argues that back in the time of the ancient Greeks and Romans, the mind was ‘bicameral’, meaning having two chambers or rooms. One side would be the self who is hearing the voice, and the other side would be the voices which would be attributed to the gods. When the idea would come ‘I must go to war’ or whatever it was, this would be the gods’ instructions rather than, as we’d think today, ‘I’ve got a good idea, let’s go to war.’

He famously says that there are no words corresponding to ‘consciousness’ in the Iliad. This argument is important for many reasons. For example, if you think about the problem of the evolution of consciousness, one question is when did it appear? Some people say it was there from the beginning of the universe – like panpsychics. But Jaynes thinks we humans only started talking and thinking about consciousness and creating the problem of consciousness within historical times and the times of literature. This is the most recent point that anyone has suggested. Further back than that, some people have suggested that you could only have consciousness if you had language. But that’s going way, way back from the written language that Jaynes talks about. So, of course, his book is going to be used as an example of the most recent origin of consciousness. But that’s not why I chose this book.

“In the time of the ancient Greeks and Romans, the mind was ‘bicameral’ – meaning having two chambers or rooms”

I chose this book because the first few chapters are the most wonderful description of the problem that I’ve come across. This is the bit I love and that I often quote. He starts off with “O, what a world of unseen visions and heard silences, this insubstantial country of the mind! What ineffable essences, these touchless rememberings and unshowable reveries!” and then says “This consciousness that is myself of selves, that is everything, and yet is nothing at all – what is it? And where did it come from? And why?”.

Then he goes into a very easy to read overview of different ideas about consciousness, constantly coming back to ‘THIS!’ and ‘WHAT IS THIS?’. This is what I do, too. I can be easily lured into stupid things like the zombie problem and thinking why aren’t I an automaton just sitting here without there being any experience? But then I come back to THIS, this moment. Jaynes is very easy to read and very prescient. His determined analysis of the problem is great, even though it was published in 1976 and we’re still struggling with it now. Obviously, he doesn’t mention the phrase ‘Hard Problem’ or any of the modern terminology, and yet I don’t think there’s any better description of the problem than the way he starts that book.

It sounds almost like David Hume’s introspective description of what he finds when he looks for his self – basically just fleeting impressions, but no enduring self. 

That’s a very good point. In a way, you could say that almost all of the books I’ve chosen are by people like that. I mentioned Descartes earlier and I should have mentioned Hume. I love how Hume looks for the self that is perceiving and finds nothing but the perceptions. That’s what one finds in meditation. I’m not a Buddhist but I’ve been practising Zen for more than 30 years. This is what you find when you look for the self. You go on and on asking, ‘who am I?’, and then you find there’s only the experiences. And even those experiences become very different when you really watch them. So, I love these people, like Descartes and Hume and Jaynes, who have really pushed their own minds and thought terribly hard about it.

Your fourth choice is The Mind’s I: Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul (1981). When I was studying philosophy of mind as an undergraduate, I found that book absolutely inspirational. It’s an amazing eclectic collection. 

When you asked earlier if I would recommend William James to the modern reader and I said what I did and offered my hesitations, I have no hesitation at all about this book because it’s got so many absolutely classic papers in it. It’s edited and introduced by [Douglas] Hofstadter and Dennett and each chapter – whether it’s written for the book or composed of excerpts or a whole paper taken from elsewhere – has a thing called ‘reflections’ at the end. Some of them are absolutely bizarre. But, again, they show people really struggling and thinking about the problems they’re dealing with, like the nature of the mind and the ‘I.’

Would you pull any chapters out as particularly interesting?

There are such classics in here. There is John Searle’s ‘Minds, Brains, and Programs’ paper, where he gives the famous Chinese Room argument. There’s also ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat?’ by Thomas Nagel. Any student interested in consciousness has to read ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat?’. That’s such a fascinating paper because Nagel thought at the time – in 1974 – that he had defeated materialism forever. He’s still more or less trying to do that today. And nobody remembers that paper for its attack on materialism. What it’s remembered for is two things. One is saying that you can never know what it’s like to be a bat. If you became a bat, you would lose all language and wouldn’t be able to tell us what it was like. Forget bats for a moment, this is one of the fundamental problems of consciousness: I can’t know what it’s like to be you, and you can’t know what it’s like to be me.

Well, I might have an idea because we are, at least, of the same species.

Yes, and we speak the same language, so we imagine we have an idea what it’s like. That’s why he chose a bat, because of course it doesn’t use vision, it uses sonar, and it’s so different from us. But the second point that people remember from this essay is the importance of thinking about what it’s like to be whatever you are. What is it like to be Nigel Warburton right now? That’s what we mean by consciousness. If there’s something that it is like for the bat to be a bat, then that’s what we mean by being conscious. If there’s nothing that it’s like to be a bat, then that’s what we mean by not being conscious. If I said ‘what is it like to be this cup?’, I hope you’d say it’s not like anything at all. And we work up from there. So, that’s a very important paper. Then, we have ‘Selfish Genes and Selfish Memes’ by Richard Dawkins. I became obsessed with memes when I re-read his The Selfish Gene when I had chronic fatigue and was in bed for a year back in 1995. To some extent I still am obsessed with them; I go backwards and forwards between consciousness and memes. That is an absolutely classic paper.

I had forgotten how rich this book is. Just to have those three is incredible. I also remember ‘Where Am I?’ by Dennett.

Yes, there’s ‘Where Am I?’ by Daniel Dennett and then there’s ‘Where Was I?’ by David Hawley Sandford; both are followed by Dennett’s reflections. There’s also ‘Ant Fugue’ by Hofstadter which is wonderful. There’s also lots by Borges himself. The first chapter in there is his ‘Borges and I.’

That’s him reflecting on the dissociation he has with the way that he appears to other people as a writer and how different that persona appears to him from the one that he feels he is, the individual who works as a librarian and walks down the street.

Yes. And if he were around today he’d have all the questions that I started asking myself when I built my first website back in the late 1990s. Who is this person that I’m putting out there? And now, when you’ve got all these social media, you feel like a different person in these different contexts. Kids nowadays are so used to that.

One more chapter is ‘On Having No Head’ by Douglas Harding. The headless way is just fantastic. After all these years of meditation, I find it very easy now to flip into the headless way. It’s another way of seeing that I am not separate from the world. I’m delighted that that article is in here, and Harding writes very succinctly and clearly about it. And then there’s Turing’s famous 1950 paper that started the Turing Test. It was called ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’ but it begins with ‘I propose to consider the question, “Can machines think?”’ That is such a classic paper. We’re still struggling with the Turing Test now and the question is ever more pertinent. Many people think that he might equally have asked not ‘can a machine think?’ but ‘can a machine be conscious?’. The question of what the relationship is between intelligence and consciousness is so hard, but nevertheless a lot of ideas about the Turing Test are used by modern people to ask whether the computer that you’re comparing to a person is conscious or not.  Those are just a few of the classics.

Support Five Books

Five Books interviews are expensive to produce. If you're enjoying this interview, please support us by .

My favourite, or at least one that really stuck with me, is by Stanisław Lem, called ‘The Seventh Sally or How Trurl’s Own Perfection Led to No Good.’ Trurl lives in this mythical kingdom ruled by a terrible tyrant who wants to murder everybody and do terrible things. Trurl is so brilliant at making tiny little machines that he makes an entire kingdom that can fit inside a case that the nasty tyrant can carry around. It had thousands of people and had fields and farms and towns and villages and uprisings and wars. It had everything all on this minute scale.

Trurl says to the king, ‘isn’t this wonderful? I can give you this tiny kingdom and you can pull levers or turn knobs to wage wars and torture people whenever you like and  yet these are all just tiny mechanisms inside a box’. The question raised at the end of the story is this: Are these tiny little insignificant people in there suffering just as the real people did? Has Trurl done a good thing or an absolutely terrible thing in creating yet another kingdom full of suffering? I love that story and the question it raises, which is not answered, of course, in the story.

I’ve put it in my consciousness textbook in all three editions, and I used it every year in my consciousness course. I would read the story to the students and ask them to write an essay or come and give a talk on whether they think that Trurl had done something really clever in stopping the suffering of the real world, or has he just created another world full of suffering? That has become more and more pertinent as AI and robots get better and better and cyberspace becomes more and more full of clever stuff. So The Mind’s I is an absolute goldmine. I would definitely recommend anyone who cares about consciousness to pick some chapters out of there or, preferably, read them all.

Your last book is a very recent one. This is Other Minds: The Octopus and the Evolution of Intelligent Life (2016) by Peter Godfrey-Smith. Until he wrote this book, he wasn’t known as an expert on octopuses.

Nor on consciousness. I should say he is a little naïve about consciousness but I think he’s a brilliant philosopher. I met him at a two-week working party at the Santa Fe Institute organised by Dennett a few years ago. He is brilliant and has the most fantastic ideas. I say that to begin with because I still want to say that I think he’s naïve about consciousness.

Even so, this book is highly relevant to consciousness and that’s why I chose it – partly too because I’ve only just read it and it’s a thrilling book to read. Again and again it makes you wonder what is it like to be an octopus? OK, a bat is pretty different from us, but a bat is a mammal. If you think about what it’s like to be a bat, you can imagine that you have wings and your little heart is beating and you have your little legs. This is because you have the same body structure as every other mammal. You have a spine and four limbs and a head. If you think about the intelligence of all other mammals, we all emerged somewhere after the dinosaurs became extinct around 65 million years ago. But the last common ancestor between us and an octopus is way back, possibly 600 million years ago. It would have been some kind of little wormy thing. The intelligence that we have must have evolved entirely separately in us, bats, whales, pussycats, and all of that, as opposed to the octopus. And there are many consequences of this for thinking about the nature of its consciousness.

“If you ask what it is like to be a certain creature, then that’s a question about consciousness”

If you ask what it is like to be a certain kind of creature, then that’s a question about consciousness. But then you try to imagine it. I cannot imagine having eight limbs, all of which are semi-autonomous. Godfrey-Smith goes into wonderful detail about how the system works. If you chop one of the tentacles off, it can still carry out meaningful movements and actions. I cannot imagine this and I cannot imagine not having a skeleton and being able to squeeze myself through the tiniest little gap and my limbs going through and then reaching out and grabbing eight things at once and doing different things with them all. It’s so hard to imagine. That’s what I loved about the book: the intricate details that he gives on octopus behaviour and on octopus evolution. This question came to my mind – if not to his – over and over again:  What is it like to be an octopus?

You said that he was naïve about consciousness. Can you say why?

Yes, only in the way that he tackles the very important and difficult question of the evolution of consciousness. In writing my textbook – in the three times I’ve done it in different editions – I’ve found it the hardest chapter to deal with. Some people, like Nicholas Humphrey, for example, start by saying that obviously we are conscious and therefore consciousness must have evolved for a function because nothing evolves that doesn’t have some kind of a function. But I don’t think that is necessarily true.

To me, the big dichotomy is this: is consciousness an added extra that appears at some stage during evolution (in which case we can ask when this happened) or is it intrinsic to being alive, or something very fundamental like that, (in which case we don’t have to ask when it evolved). For example, I could take the view that as soon as anything has a representation of itself in the world or makes any kind of distinction between inside and outside – this is me and this is the outside world – then ‘what it is like to be’ it would be whatever that distinction describes. In that case, a bacterium which has a membrane and chemical sensors and goes towards some chemicals and away from others, has got some kind of very basic representation of this and that. If you ask ‘what is it like to be’ that bacterium, then I would say it’s what it is like to be that representation.

This is an idea that I have toyed with for a long time in different versions. If we take it up to cats and dogs, then this is very complex thinking. It gets even more complicated with humans, with all their delusions and their illusion of self and so on. With any view of that kind – and there are plenty of related views of this kind – you don’t need to ask when consciousness arose. You don’t ask when it emerged, because it is absolutely intrinsic to everything else that is going on. But Godfrey-Smith doesn’t raise that problem at all. He just asks when it arose and tries to find out by looking at the different things that different organisms do. The book’s not all about consciousness, but the chapter he has on the evolution of consciousness doesn’t really engage well with the current arguments that are very deep and very difficult about what we mean by the evolution of consciousness. Nevertheless, running through that book all the time is this question of what it is like to be an octopus.

It is a brilliantly written book and absolutely gripping (and, as I mentioned, I find it hard to be gripped by a book.) So, I’ve included it among my five choices as a much more light-hearted option– something that’s an enjoyable read that will also make you think.

Interview by Nigel Warburton

January 31, 2018

Five Books aims to keep its book recommendations and interviews up to date. If you are the interviewee and would like to update your choice of books (or even just what you say about them) please email us at [email protected]

Susan Blackmore

Susan Blackmore

Sue Blackmore is a psychologist, lecturer and writer researching consciousness, memes, and anomalous experiences. She is a visiting professor at the University of Plymouth, a TED lecturer and blogger for the Guardian. Her book The Meme Machine (1999) has been translated into 16 languages; more recent books include Conversations on Consciousness (2005), Zen and the Art of Consciousness (2011), and Seeing Myself: The New Science of Out-of-Body Experiences (2017).

Susan Blackmore

Susan Blackmore

Sue Blackmore is a psychologist, lecturer and writer researching consciousness, memes, and anomalous experiences. She is a visiting professor at the University of Plymouth, a TED lecturer and blogger for the Guardian. Her book The Meme Machine (1999) has been translated into 16 languages; more recent books include Conversations on Consciousness (2005), Zen and the Art of Consciousness (2011), and Seeing Myself: The New Science of Out-of-Body Experiences (2017).