Nigel Warburton’s recommendations

An interview with...

Nigel Warburton on Introductions to Philosophy

About Nigel Warburton

Nigel Warburton is a freelance philosopher, writer and podcaster. He is best known for his introductory philosophy books and for his podcast series, Philosophy Bites. Featuring short interviews with the world's best philosophers on bite-size topics, the podcast has been downloaded more than 11 million times to date. His latest book is A Little History of Philosophy.

Image by h.koppdelaney on Flickr

How should we live? What is the nature of reality? Should pro golfers be allowed to use carts? The philosophy lecturer sets us off down the road of philosophical enquiry with an intriguing reading list

How did you first become interested in philosophy?

I can remember as a very young child asking the question, "How does a baby learn to speak?" I wasn't really satisfied with the answer my mother gave me – that you just point to things and say their names. I'm not sure I could answer the question now, but it was certainly of philosophical interest. As a teenager, I also picked out Bertrand Russell's History of Western Philosophy from the local public library, which was one of the great inspirations for me. The library, that is, rather than the book. I think it's the route out of suburbia for a lot of people. It opened up different sorts of reading for me. I would walk several miles to the local library and take out as many books as I could. Inevitably, sooner or later I got some philosophy books, along with all sorts of weird and wonderful ones.

What did you make of the Russell book?

It wasn't the book I needed at that age. I've since tried to write that book a couple of times, but I don't know if I've succeeded. It was a bit slow-moving for me and I didn't get beyond the pre-Socratics, who didn't really stimulate me.

So did you really get into the subject at university?

I actually went to Bristol University to study psychology, but I became a bit disillusioned with it and dropped out. After a year out from university, that I mostly spent working as a car park attendant, the decisive factor for me about going back to university to study philosophy rather than psychology was that there was a clash between the two courses. I was very interested in reading Sartre and I wouldn't have been able to study Sartre's Being and Nothingness in psychology. That clash made me realise how much I wanted to understand that book, or at least parts of it. That was my one opportunity, I felt, because it isn't the kind of book you can make sense of on your own. So I switched to philosophy.

It seems a lot of Anglo-American philosophers are drawn into the subject as teenagers by their encounters with existentialism, and especially Sartre. But often, after a certain number of years of study, they come to strongly disagree with Sartre's philosophy. Did that happen to you?

I don't think you have to agree with the philosophers you read. It's almost better if you disagree with them because then you have some kind of dialogue – you don't read them in a passive way. I find Sartre stimulating, difficult and frustrating. His later writings are unreadable, driven by his use of the drug speed and written with no concessions to the reader. So the fact that I disagree with huge amounts of what Sartre said doesn't mean that he wasn't an amazing and important thinker to me.

Sartre was also a novelist, and his novels are often described as philosophical. Do you think novels and novelists can really engage in philosophy, or is that only possible if you're a professional academic philosopher?

I think professional philosophers often like to make their subject smaller than it really is by setting arbitrary limits. As far as I'm concerned, philosophy is any human enterprise that involves critical thought about basic questions, like how we should live, what is the nature of reality and so on. Those questions can be asked seriously in all kinds of forms. So I don't see the subject as restricted to nerdy philosophical papers in refereed journals. Some of the most important contributions have been literary. If you think of classical philosophy, you have Plato's very literary dialogues, and Lucretius's On The Nature of Things is a poem! Some parts of TS Eliot's poems are very philosophical. Kierkegaard is a poetic writer who uses fictions, and Nietzsche uses aphorisms and poetry. They're all philosophers.

Do you think, given the success of your podcast series Philosophy Bites, that there has been increased interest in philosophy over the past 30 years?

There may have been the same appetite for philosophy back then, but it wasn't necessarily filled in a palatable way. When I began writing introductory philosophy books in the late 1980s, the only introductions that were readily available were The Problems of Philosophy by Bertrand Russell, which was published in 1912, and a book called Philosophy Made Simple – which was actually a good book, but people found the title off-putting because it sounded like it was dumbing the subject down. If you go into a bookshop now there would be a whole bookcase of introductory books, but 20 years ago there were surprisingly few philosophy books designed for the general reader.

When I was teaching A level [high school] philosophy students and undergraduates, I was aware that there were no books to help people make the transition from an interest in philosophy to being able to read some of the classics. So I wrote a book called Philosophy: TheBasics. Most university teachers would say you don't really need an introduction, you can just go and read Hume or Descartes or Mill. But many readers can't get through that sort of writing and gain an overview of the key points without a bit of help.

Let's talk about your first choice, What Does It All Mean? by Thomas Nagel.

I just dug through my bookshelves looking for this but I couldn't find it. I've had a number of copies of this book but I always seem to end up giving it away, which I think is a good sign.

Why is it such a good gateway into the subject?

It's perfect for someone who wants to find out what philosophy is all about. First of all, it's very, very short. Secondly, it's written in prose that is completely unpretentious, unpatronising and clear. It's the kind of book you could read in an evening, but at the same time you'd really have a flavour of what philosophy is. It's got the authority of him being a significant philosopher in his own right, but if you had no idea who he was it wouldn't matter. The writing is almost Orwellian in its simplicity and directness. As somebody who has tried to write clear introductory books, I know how difficult that is to pull off.

Nagel begins with the observation – which mirrors my experience as a teacher and as a father – that philosophy arises naturally out of the human condition. People start asking philosophical questions from an early age. And there is a history of over 2,000 years of people discussing these questions – thinking critically about how we should live, what the nature of reality is, what consciousness is. Nagel goes through all these major areas of philosophy with a very light touch.

“What does it all mean?” is a question that people who haven't studied philosophy often think the subject is about. They might be a little disappointed, if they study it formally, to discover that there is little talk about the meaning of life and so on. Do you think the title might give readers false expectations?

In the introduction to the book, Nagel writes, "There isn’t much you can assume or take for granted. So philosophy is a somewhat dizzying activity, and few of its results go unchallenged for long." He's not pretending philosophy is going to tell you what it all means. It's going to introduce you to the questions and help you think critically about them. If somebody comes to philosophy thinking they are going to come out after a few years understanding exactly how we should live and what reality is like, then they're naive. That's one of the things you learn from studying philosophy. As Socrates pointed out, true wisdom lies in knowing how little you know.

The next book is The Life You Can Save by Peter Singer, who is perhaps the most famous living philosopher.

I was thinking, “How would you introduce philosophy to someone who didn't know anything about it?” I think the central question in philosophy is, “How should we live?” And that's a question about which Peter Singer has a lot to say.

What is the central message of the book?

The book focuses on the terrible poverty and disease found around the world, and how we in the West are living in a luxury that we could adjust just a little bit in order to alleviate that misery. He suggests that we give maybe 5% of our wages to charity. He's not saying you have to live in a sackcloth and give away all your possessions. Even a small gift of 5% would make a tremendous difference to other people's lives. It's not just him preaching, he gives arguments for his positions. And even if you disagree with him, the process of reading his work makes you think, “Why do I disagree?” He is in the tradition of Socrates – somebody who challenges your preconceptions and asks you to respond.

How does the book begin?

Singer starts with a compelling thought experiment. Imagine you're passing a pond. There's a young child drowning in the pond and his head's just about to go underwater. You're on your way to work, you're nicely dressed. But you'd surely jump in the pond and try to save the child, wouldn't you? Almost anyone would do that unthinkingly, even though it would ruin their expensive clothes and make them late for work. Yet in our everyday lives, we know that through inaction we are allowing children to die of poverty who could otherwise be saved by a minimal contribution – less than the price of an expensive pair of shoes.

What's the difference between the situation described in the thought experiment and our inaction in everyday life? Singer thinks that there isn't an important moral difference. He says there are ways in which we could act that would be the equivalent of saving the drowning child's life – giving to charities that tackle poverty, disease and so on. He believes most of us could be much more generous at very little cost to our own lives, and that the result of this would be of huge measurable benefit to mankind.

That sounds like a persuasive argument in theory. What are the objections?

Singer is brilliant because you don't have to agree with him, but he goes through all the standard objections to his view and presents counterarguments. Someone might say, “The difference is that if I save the child myself I know the child is going to be saved, but if I give my money to a charity it might be wasted.” Well, there's a website that has been set up which analyses the comparative effects of money sent to different charities. It comes up with charities where the effect your donation is most likely to save lives. So Singer has second-guessed you, and come up with a counterargument and a practical way of implementing the conclusion he'd like you to embrace.

What do you think of Singer's work more generally?

Singer is incredibly consistent in his positions. He used to be a chess player, but he believes that the point of philosophy is not to solve chess-like problems but actually to make a difference. If you really believe, as he does, in a form of utilitarianism – the view that the consequences of our actions determine their rightness or wrongness – then that's not just an intellectual position, it should affect how you live. Singer is a counter-example to the stereotype of the philosopher in an ivory tower, whose life makes no difference, who leaves everything as it is.

Your third book, Justice by Michael Sandel, discusses political philosophy rather than ethics.

The reason I picked this book is because I think Michael Sandel is an outstanding speaker and writer in his ability to bring philosophy alive. He can take a thinker like Aristotle and make him completely relevant to the present day, to show how his ideas have applications in our everyday lives.

Can you give an example?

There was a golfer named Casey Martin. He was an excellent golfer, but he had a problem with his leg. There was a whole dispute about whether he should be allowed a golf cart to get around the course. There were even court cases about it. Sandel shows how the debates that arose about this issue were extremely Aristotelian in nature. They come down to questions like “what is golf?”, “what is the essence of golf?” and “what is the purpose of playing golf?” Is it a sport where the emphasis is all on the hitting of the ball into the hole, or is there – as some golfers argued – a physical endurance element as well? Is it unfair if one person is whizzing around on a golf cart whilst others are tiring themselves out walking around the course? Does that mean they're going to be at a disadvantage in relation to this guy on the golf cart? And so on.

To resolve these questions, we need to think about the ultimate purpose – what Aristotle would call the telos – of golf. But these questions also turn on questions of honour and prestige attached to the notion of physical endurance. Sandel adds a really nice observation here. He discusses how some golfers are touchy about how their sport is not a physical sport, so they have a vested interest in it seeming physically demanding. Sandel has also been extremely good at using the Internet to encourage people across the world to engage with his ideas. His justice course at Harvard is available on YouTube.

Sandel is primarily a political philosopher. Obviously, philosophy is very rigorous and helps train one to think critically. But do you think knowledge of philosophical ideas themselves is helpful to politicians?

Many politicians have studied philosophy, and that undoubtedly influences their thinking to some degree. There are very few examples of contemporary philosophers who have dramatically changed the course of politics. But there are some: Karl Popper, John Rawls and, in the modern era, Sandel to some degree. But possibly more important has been Philip Pettit, whose ideas were taken up by the Spanish prime minister, José Luis Rodriguez Zapatero. Pettit was actually invited in to assess Zapatero's government according to the philosophical principles of republicanism. Pettit famously gave it nine out of 10. The idea that a contemporary philosopher should be involved with that kind of activity is really interesting. But for the most part, the study of abstract ideas with particular attention to reasoning is simply a useful skill for politicians. Of course you could be a Marxist and apply a single philosophical theory to every case, but what I'd prefer in a democracy is politicians who are prepared to think on their feet about changing situations, rather than just apply a ready-made theory and read off the conclusions.

Your next choice, Causing Death and Saving Lives by the English philosopher Jonathan Glover, is another work on moral philosophy.

When I was an undergraduate, this book made me think philosophy was really worth studying. It showed me that philosophy isn't nitpicking or school debating societies, but rather a subject that gets right to the heart of what matters. Like Peter Singer, Glover believes that your thinking about philosophical issues should make a difference to your life.

Is that view unusual among professional philosophers?

It's surprisingly unusual among academic philosophers – or it certainly was when he wrote the book in the 1970s. At that time, most moral philosophy was focused on very abstract questions in meta-ethics. Glover was an important part of a movement towards looking at real-life problems. This book looks at questions surrounding abortion, euthanasia, suicide and killing in war. The common thread is the theme of the morality of killing.

How does Glover differ from Peter Singer?

Glover is as likely to quote Dostoevsky, Orwell or other literary writers as he is to quote philosophers. There's an extremely humane feel to his work. He wants to combine the insights of utilitarianism with those of Kant – the idea that individual human autonomy is important and shouldn't be overridden. That latter point is sometimes overlooked by utilitarian thinking. Glover is very good on questions about the sanctity of life. A lot of religious people believe that all human life is sacred and that it's wrong to end a life ever. Glover's emphasis is on a life worth living. He argues that there must come points where, for some individuals, life simply isn't worth living.

Your last book is a bit of a curveball. I can't say I've ever heard of The Grasshopper by Bernard Suits before.

I hadn't heard of it myself until GA Cohen recommended it to me a few years ago. And then, independently, Simon Blackburn recommended it. So I thought given these recommendations from eminent philosophers, there must be something to it. It's a slim book, first published in 1978. It's all about playing games. Not only is that an interesting subject for a book, but it's also written in a light-hearted way. It actually exemplifies some of what it's arguing for.

What does it argue?

One way of reading the book is as a critique of Wittgenstein's “family resemblance argument” about games. Wittgenstein says that there is no one thing in common that is shared by all games. Instead, there's just a pattern of overlapping resemblances between the things we happen to call games. There's no single, essential aspect of all games. Well, Bernard Suits thinks you can actually give a definition of games according to necessary and sufficient conditions. That makes it sound dry but it's not a book about definition.

Why is the book called The Grasshopper?

It's called The Grasshopper because the central character is, in fact, a grasshopper! It's inspired by Aesop's fable about the grasshopper and the ant. The industrious ant works all summer and survives the winter, whereas the grasshopper spends his time dancing and singing, so he has nothing to eat and starves to death. But at the same time, it's a parody of a Socratic dialogue with the grasshopper in the role of Socrates, dying of starvation but choosing to die rather than give up his belief that the thing which has intrinsic value in life is play. He'd rather die of starvation than give that up.

Is the book for children as well as adults?

Oh no, it's a book written for philosophers primarily. That's what makes it so clever. It actually puts forward a whole theory about the nature of game playing. Suits argues that playing a game is "the voluntary attempt to overcome unnecessary obstacles”. Basically there are three features to all games, and for something to be a game it has to meet all these features. Games must have the "pre-lusory goal", constitutive rules and the "lusory attitude".

The pre-lusory goal is the purpose of a game. Take mountaineering. The pre-lusory goal is getting to the top of the mountain. Now you could get to the top of the mountain by parachuting in from a helicopter. But for something to be a game it needs to have rules, which might exclude certain ways of achieving the pre-lusory goal. And then there is the third part, the lusory attitude – namely that you accept the rules not just because you have to. It's all about participating in the spirit of the game. You're following those rules because you want to.

This book is written in dialogue form, which is very unusual in modern philosophy. How does it work?

A few of the classic works of philosophy have been written as dialogues – Plato's works of course, and also one of my favourite books, David Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. But it's amazing how few successful dialogues there are in philosophy, given those great exemplars. The Grasshopper is Suits's serious attempt to do it in a lighthearted way. Without being po-faced, Suits has found a way to make serious philosophical points.

And why is Suits so interested in games in the first place?

He believes that game-playing is the highest good, because in a utopian world where all our other needs are met, he believes human beings would just play games. They'd set themselves obstacles and willingly try to achieve these pre-lusory goals. They wouldn't need to worry about anything else. If heaven were real, that's how we would survive in eternity. Suits thinks games are the highest intrinsic good. That might be going a bit far, but he's found a light-hearted way of getting to that conclusion – by using arguments and considering counter-examples.

He builds in lots of jokes and he's a skillful writer. Unlike the other writers on my list, he draws attention to his style. You can't read this without noticing he’s playing with form. It's a nice short book that deserves to be better known. It's mysterious that it's been so neglected, particularly given all the interest in Wittgenstein's theories about games.



Books by Nigel Warburton

Good choices? What's missing? Write your thoughts below